Thursday, April 24, 2014
Exit from comment view mode. Click to hide this space
7

Natural-Born Pianists?

LONDON – The editor of The Guardian, Alan Rusbridger, has written a book about how he decided to practice the piano 20 minutes a day. Eighteen months later, he played Chopin’s fearsomely difficult Ballade No. 1 in G Minor to an admiring audience of friends. Could anyone have done this? Or did it require special talent?

The nature-versus-nurture debate has been around a long time. It is unresolved because the scientific question has always been entangled with politics. Broadly speaking, those stressing inborn capacity have been political conservatives; those emphasizing nurture have been political radicals.

The nineteenth-century philosopher John Stuart Mill was of the “anyone can do it” school. He was convinced that his achievements were in no way due to superior heredity: anyone of “normal intelligence and health,” subjected to his father’s educational system – which included learning Greek at the age of three – could have become John Stuart Mill.

Mill was part of his century’s liberal attack on aristocratic privilege: achievement was the result of opportunity, not birth. The practice of the faculties (education) unleashes potential that would otherwise remain dormant.

Charles Darwin seemingly overturned this optimistic view of the potential beneficial effects of nurture. Species evolve, Darwin said, through “natural selection” – the random selection, through competition, of biological traits favorable to survival in a world of scarce resources. Herbert Spencer used the phrase “survival of the fittest” to explain how societies evolve.

Social Darwinists interpreted natural selection to mean that any humanitarian effort to improve the condition of the poor would impede the progress of the human race by burdening it with an excess of drones. Society would be spending scarce resources on losers rather than winners. This fit the ideology of a brand of capitalism that was “red in tooth and claw.”

Indeed, social Darwinism provided a pseudo-scientific justification for the American belief in laissez-faire (with the successful businessman epitomizing the survival of the fittest); for eugenics (the deliberate attempt to breed superior individuals, on the model of horse-breeding, and prevent the “over-breeding” of the unfit); and for the eugenic-cum-racial theories of Nazism.

In reaction to social Darwinism’s murderous tendencies, Mill’s view became dominant after World War II in the form of social democracy. State action to improve diet, education, health, and housing would enable the poor to realize their potential. Competition as a social principle was downgraded in favor of cooperation.

Differences in innate ability were not denied (at least by the sensible). But it was rightly felt that there was a huge amount of work to be done to raise average levels of achievement before one needed to start worrying that one’s policies were promoting the survival of the unfit.

Then the mood began to shift again. Social democracy was attacked for penalizing the successful and rewarding the unsuccessful. In 1976, the biologist Richard Dawkins identified the unit of Darwinian selection as the “selfish gene.” The evolutionary story was now recast as a battle of genes to secure their survival over time by means of mutations, which create individuals (phenotypes) best adapted to pass on their genes. In the course of evolution, the inferior phenotypes disappear.

Although this view of evolution would not have been possible before the discovery of DNA, it is no coincidence that it rose to prominence in the age of Ronald Reagan and Margaret Thatcher. To be sure, the selfish gene needs to be “altruistic” insofar as its survival depends on the survival of the kinship group. But it need not be that altruistic. And, although Dawkins later regretted calling his gene “selfish” (he says that “immortal” would have been better), his choice of adjective was certainly best adapted to maximizing sales of his book at that particular time.

Since then, we have turned away from advocacy of selfishness, but we have not recovered an independent moral language. The new orthodoxy, suitable for a world in which the unrestrained pursuit of greed has proved economically disastrous, is that the human species is genetically programmed to be moral, because only by acting morally (caring for the survival of others) can it ensure its long-term survival.

The “hard-wiring” metaphor dominates contemporary moral language. According to the United Kingdom’s chief rabbi, Jonathan Sacks, religious beliefs are useful for our survival, by inducing us to act in socially cooperative ways: “We have mirror neurons that lead us to feel pain when we see others suffering,” he recently wrote. Consideration for others is “located in the prefrontal cortex.” And religion “reconfigures our neural pathways.” In short: “Far from refuting religion, the Neo-Darwinists have helped us understand why it matters.” So we need not fear that it will decline.

Atheists might not agree. But it is an extraordinary statement for a religious leader to make, because it sets to one side the question of the truth or falsehood, or the ethical value, of religious beliefs. Or rather: all that wiring in the prefrontal cortex must be ethical, because it is good for survival. But, in that case, what ethical value is there in survival? Does the continued survival of the human race have any value in itself, independent of what we achieve or create?

We need to rescue morality from the claims of science. We need to assert what philosophers and religious teachers have at all times asserted: that there is something called the good life, apart from survival, and our understanding of it has to be taught, just as Mill’s father taught him the elements of Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics. Our nature may predispose us to learn; but what we learn depends on how we are nurtured.

Exit from comment view mode. Click to hide this space
Hide Comments Hide Comments Read Comments (7)

Please login or register to post a comment

  1. CommentedAidan Kelly

    The piece is a good reminder of the evolution of human thought and awareness about who we are. The sentence "We need to rescue morality from the claims of science" should read "We need to rescue morality from the claims of science and religion". Religion is not morality when it is used to pit Person A against Person B or to exploit the trust of otherwise innocent persons.

  2. CommentedJ. T. G.

    Skidelsky posed the question "Does the continued survival of the human race have any value in itself, independent of what we achieve or create?"

    I pose the questions - is the earth a better place because humans evolved to what we are? would the earth be a better place if humans never evolved at all?

  3. Commentedradek tanski

    Mises said that ultimately democracy was about protecting the majority from the minority. Similarly in the finishing paragraph it seems that ethics needs some help to triumph against science and logic.

    So what is it that the dangerous minority in parallel with science and logic over ethics and morality has? And more importantly why does evolution see fit to make this minority so tenacious?

    Perhaps popular economists are pandering to the masses for possible political gains?

  4. CommentedFrank O'Callaghan

    "Social Darwinism" was never intellectually respectable. It always reeked of what it was: a pathetic excuse for communally destructive theft. Dawkins could hardly have called his work the "immortal" gene as his whole point was that most genetic units become extinct and those that survive do so by adapting.
    Science says nothing on morality- nor can it. Skidelsky is correct that there is something all recognize as the good life. The world has enough resources today to provide it for all. Failing to do so is criminal.

  5. CommentedProcyon Mukherjee

    I fully endorse what Vineet Bewtra has said on Mutual Aid and who can forget Kropotkin’s central argument, “The animal species, in which individual struggle has been reduced to its narrowest limits, and the practice of mutual aid has attained the greatest development, are invariably the most numerous, the most prosperous and the most open to further progress.”

    The world would have been a different place if Kropotkin’s theme could have progressed more amongst the people than the more insidious argument about selfish nature of our existence that go against the historicity of human progress that achieved more through cooperation than through the narrowness of plundering and pillaging for furthering self-appropriation and power. The vacuous nature of our understanding of what entails human skills, expertise and prowess, has the final test in the battle field where human endurance rests on the shoulders of fellow-brethrens who must collaborate seamlessly for survival; there can be no other better example that could refute or explain why survival is so innately associated with mutual aid.



  6. Commenteddonna jorgo

    human mind is complication IS HOW OTHERS UNDERSTANTED ..HOW YOU SAID ...PLAYING ORGAN MUSICE IS TALENT EVEN SOME ONE LEARN IN FACULTET THIS IS NOT THE SAME WITH ONE IS FENOMENAL ..BUT BECAUSE YOUR COLUMN HAVE OTHER SIDE OF MEANING i have to say again is ..how understanding ..TRY TO UNDERSTAND THE HUMAN MINDE (BETTER BEFFOR CONCLUTION WRITING)
    I AM NOT AGREE WITH YOUR ARTICLE ..

  7. CommentedVineet Bewtra

    The piece reminded me a lot about Kropotkin's Mutual Aid argument which I think has been overlooked by too many (especially among the market- or competition- ideologues, which did indeed include Thatcher et al).

    The call for rescuing morality from science seems nice in principle, but seems to be based on assuming a valued position for homo sapiens. If we work on the basis that nature is indifferent to which species survive or not, then there does not need to be an ethical value for survival - indeed, a norm-driven calling for something "superior" may then seem, well, self-indulgent for any species.

    Perhaps I misinterpret it, but Mutual Aid always seemed like showing why co-operation is also vitally important. That may seem instrumentalist, but I don't see why that takes away from the beauty or resonance (or normative value) of ethics, empathy or co-operation. Certainly co-operation needs to be brought back in to the tent - pure competition is not enough and seems like an evolutionarily-foolish strategy to use exclusively?

Featured